Speaking III of the Dead
Those who tell us that we ought not to speak ill of the dead do not merely mean that we ought not to slander the dead. For it is obviously our duty to abstain from slandering not only the dead but also the living. The precept evidently requires us to make a difference between our way of speaking of the living and of the dead. When we speak of the living, we may mention both their good and bad qualities; but is speaking of the dead we are to say all the good we can of them and never mention anything to their discredit.
The spirit of this maxim is always followed in the composition of epitaphs. There is a well-known story of how someone, going through a churchyard and reading the inscriptions on the tomb. stones, asked in astonishment where all the bad people were buried. The reason of his question was that, while many of the epitaphs commemorated the virtues of the dead, none of them contained a single word of blame.
We have, then, to consider how far this lenient treatment of the character of the dead is justifiable. Two very good reasons can certainly be urged against speaking of the faults of the dead In the first place it seems unjust and cowardly to accuse those who are unable to defend themselves. In the second place, speaking ill of the dead may give great pain to their living relations and friends. The second .reason only applies to the case of those who are recently dead. We are not likely to hurt any one’s feelings by mentioning the faults of Alexander the Great or Napoleon. No one would maintain that historians and students of history should not do their best to form an impartial estimate of the characters of great men. Such a prohibition would deprive the world of the valuable moral lessons that history gives, when it affords us conspicuous examples of the defects that have marred- the careers of eminent men. Also the greatest virtue of the historian is truth, and truth is incompatible with the concealment of the \faults of historical characters.
It may be objected that it is equally contrary to truth to abstain in conversation from speaking of the faults of the recently dead. But this is not the case. The historian professes to give, in accordance with the facts of history, an impartial account of the historical characters about whom he writes; -but in ordinary conversation about private persons we do not profess to give care-fully balanced estimates of character, and’ no one is likely to be deceived unless we ascribe to those of whom we are speaking virtues which they do riot possess. Therefore, although we cannot go so far as to say that we should never speak ill of the dead, there is no reason why we should not as a general rule avoid saying anything to their discredit, particularly as in this fault finding world there is no fear of the worst side of any one’s character being forgotten after death.